Catholicism and Religious Thought
[The Contemporary Review, May 1885]
{652} THE purpose of these papers is to attempt a critical analysis and
appraisement of those principles of the English Catholic movement that
may be held to have significance for constructive religious thought.
The point from which the second or material part of the discussion can
best start is the relation of the English to the earlier Continental
Catholic revival. The former had a distinctive character of its own;
but it would be a grave mistake to regard it either as single and
isolated, or as simply the creation of a few able and resolute men.
That was what it seemed to many contemporary critics, but it was
nothing so accidental and arbitrary. It stood connected with and
represented a tendency that had been active in European thought and
life, the reaction against the Illumination and the Revolution. The
reaction was not simple but complex, at once religious, intellectual
and political; a recoil of the conservative spirit from the new ideals
that had been so suddenly translated into portentous realities. It was
marked everywhere by the same hatred of the eighteenth century and all
its works, embodied everywhere the same hopes and fears, expressed the
same motives and ends. On the one side stood the revolutionary theses,
the rights of reason and of man, the watchwords liberty, equality,
fraternity. These the reaction construed not in their high ideal
sense, but through the accidents and atrocities, the terror and ruin
that had attended the attempt at realization; and over against them
emphasized its own antitheses—the rights of the community before
those of the individual, the rights of God and the sovereigns,
spiritual and civil, He appointed above those of the reason and the
peoples, authority as the only sufficient basis of order, and order as
the condition necessary to the highest common good. But not satisfied
with opposing antitheses to theses, it confronted {653} recent with
mediæval history, idealized it, attempted to resuscitate and realize
its ideals, and invested the Church—which was its most splendid and
persistent creation—with the authority that alone could revive
religion and create order, curb and turn back the loosened and lawless
forces of revolution. This radical contradiction, ideal and
historical, seemed the surest as the most direct way to victory; but
to build a dam across a river is not to arrest the gathering and
course of its waters, as the men who securely pitch their tents in the
shelter of the dam will be the first to experience.
I.
The Catholic revival was the principal phase or
feature of the reaction, and the literature that was its most
operative factor may be described as the literature of the new
Catholic Apologetic [Note 1]. Our
reference to its distinctive principles and work must be brief.
1. The reaction was a complex movement, at once
literary, political, religious. In literature it appeared as
Romanticism, in politics as legitimate and theocratic theory, in
religion as Ultramontanism. These three were but different phases or
expressions of the one spirit, representing, as it were, the
organization of the more conservative instincts against the new
agencies of progress and change. The oneness of the spirit is evident
from the ease with which its phases melted or passed into each other.
Romanticism appeared, indeed, outside Catholicism, was German, the
creation of men like the Schlegels, Tieck, Novalis, who loved the
realm of the imagination, and hated the rationalism that had expelled
miracle from Nature, and mystery from man, making the universe the
home of prosaic commonplace. They disliked the cold classicism of
Goethe and the warmer humanism of Schiller, and said: "Poetry and
religion are one; man needs an imagination to interpret the universe,
and a universe peopled by it and for it; when he has most religion he
has most imagination, and the times when he had both in the highest
degree were the mediæval." And so they glorified these times, edited
their ballads and romances, praised their ideal of life and duty,
their bravery, courtesy, devotion; their indifference to the market
and the exchange, their loyalty to beauty and honour and religion,
their glorious Gothic architecture, with the faith it at once {654}
embodied, illustrated and made illustrious. Admiration for the past,
though it was a past that was a pure creature of the imagination,
easily became belief in the Church that claimed it, and so Romanticism
in men like Stolberg, Friedrich Schlegel, and Werner, passed by a
natural gradation into Catholicism.
The reaction in politics was conducted in a still
more courageous and thorough spirit, for it was directly polemical, a guerre
à outrance. Authority must be made divine if the rights of man
were to be denied and his reason subdued and governed; but the
dynastic idea had been too rudely broken to be capable of again
standing up, and in its own name claiming divine authority. Its hour
of weakness was the Church's opportunity; it alone had braved the
storm, it had been shaken but it had stood, manifestly, not in its own
strength, but in God's. In the lurid light of the anarchy Rome was
seen to have a mission; as the seat and home of supreme authority,
universal, immutable, infallible, she could stand forward as the
saviour of society, now gone or going to destruction for want of its
most Christian kings. She was the Church God had founded, had
supernaturally endowed and guided, had made the sole bearer and
teacher of His truth, and had graced and crowned with an Infallible
Head. Here was an authority so awful, so august, and so inviolable as
to be alone able to end the conflict of rival rights, and restore
order by enforcing the one universal duty—obedience. If divine
authority was to rule in the State, it must be got through the Church.
And so Joseph de Maistre formulated his hierocratic doctrine, making
the Papal at once guarantee and condition the royal power. De Bonald
wove the political into the religious revelation, ascribing sole
sovereignty to God, but building upon it the Pope's, and upon his the
king's. Chateaubriand described Christian Rome as being for the modern
what Pagan Rome had been for the ancient world—the universal bond of
nations, instructing in duty, defending from oppression. Lamennais
argued that without authority there could be no religion, that it was
the foundation of all society and morality, and that it alone
enfranchized man by making him obedient, so harmonizing all
intelligences and wills. And thus the Church, as the supreme
authority, became the principle of order, the centre of political as
well as religious stability; the only divine rights were those she
sanctioned, in her strength kings reigned, and through obedience to
her man was happy and God honoured.
2. The Revolution thus gave Catholicism a
splendid opportunity for a new Apologetic; summoned it to occupy a
more important and commanding position than it had held since the fall
of Rome. The Apologetic may be described as the theory of the
position, or the principle of authority done into the philosophy, of
the counter-revolution. It may be said to have consisted of two parts,
a theoretical {655} and an historical—the first being a vindication
of authority as the only sure basis of religion, and, consequently,
the only solid ground and guarantee of order; the second being a
justification of the Roman Church as it had lived and acted in
history. On the positive side it was a philosophy of religion,
society, and history; on the negative, an absolute contradiction of
the modern philosophies, the governing principles or ideas of the
modern mind. The Apologists saw that the Revolution had not been an
accident, but a logical issue from the premisses of the sixteenth
century; an attempt to realize a political ideal correlative and
correspondent to the ideal of religious freedom. The anarchy, the
bloodshed, the social misery and ruin, were held to be the direct
result of the movement then instituted; to this, along many lines, it
had been inevitably tending; in this, its true character stood
revealed. What appeared before the Revolution as innocent
abstractions, or speculations that flattered human pride in the degree
that they exercised human reason, appeared after it as disintegrative
forces capable of doing the most disastrous work. It was not a
question of Catholicism against Protestantism, but of Catholicism
against the modern movement as a whole. Humanity must be turned back
in its course three centuries that society might be saved. The
literary revolt of the fifteenth century, the religious revolt of the
sixteenth, the philosophical systems of the seventeenth, the political
revolution of the eighteenth, were all parts of a whole, successive
steps in the dread argument that had been fulfilling itself in
history. To deal with this in the most radical way, modern philosophy,
as supplying the principles and premisses, was fiercely attacked. De
Maistre held Bacon to be a presumptuous and profane scientific
charlatan, whose bad philosophy was the fit expression of his bad
morality. And in censure he was quite impartial: "Contempt of Locke
was the beginning of knowledge." [Note
2] Hume "was perhaps the most dangerous and the guiltiest of all
those baleful writers who will for ever accuse the last century before
posterity." [Note 3] Voltaire "was
a man Paris crowned, but Sodom would have banished." [Note
4] Lamennais argued that the philosophies and the heresies had one
principle, "la souveraineté de la raison humaine," the end whereof
was universal disbelief [Note 5].
Admit it, and from the end there was no escape; the inevitable way was
from heresy to deism, from deism to atheism, from atheism to universal
scepticism. Hence, by an exhaustive process, the necessary conclusion
was reached: we must have authority if we are to have faith; the true
religion is that which rests on the greatest visible authority, which
from sheer lack of actual or possible claimants can be no other than
Rome. The {656} variations of philosophers as of Protestants proved
their want of truth; the consistencies and harmonies of Catholics
proved their possession of it. Authority being the creative and
fundamental principle in religion, to despise or deny it was
sin—order was Heaven's first law; contempt of authority man's first
disobedience. The systems that denied it were not simply false, they
were evil; at once causes and fruits of sin. Of sin and its inexorable
penalties, the new Apologetic had much to say; sin explained the
revolt, the revolution illustrated the penalty. To end the revolt the
Church must triumph; and its victory would be the creation, not of
religion only, but of order, of a stable, contented, happy society.
But, as Lamennais was destined later fatefully to discover, if
authority was to rule at all, it must rule everywhere, in both Church
and State; if freedom reigned in either, it would reign in both. So De
Maistre saw and victoriously argued: both authorities are of God, but
the spiritual is the higher; the king's does not qualify the Pope's,
but the Pope's limits the king's. Power may be limited from above, but
not from below; the subjects may not judge the sovereign, or impose
conditions on him, but the Pope may, and his judge is God. Authority,
thus absolute, political, personified in the king, confronted
revolution; spiritual, personified in the Pope, confronted reason; and
by its strength religion was to be saved, society re-constituted,
order created, and humanity made obedient to God.
But it was not enough to be critical and
theoretical; it was no less necessary to show the fine correspondence
of the theory with history, the speculation with fact. And so the
discussion became historical; the Church was exhibited as the maker of
civilization, the mother of the arts and sciences, the creator of the
humanities, the enemy of vice, the nurse of virtue, the home of all
the graces. When the Roman empire fell she mitigated the miseries,
lessened the evils, conserved the good that but for her had perished
in the ruins. When the young peoples came pouring into the older
States, she received them into her bosom, tamed them, organized their
energies, built them into a new order and new civilization. She
protected its tender years; hers was the arm which turned back the
Moor, the Saracen, and the Turk. In her the conquered peoples had
their true and strongest friend; the conquerors, a common sovereign
who ruled their fierce wills into obedience and humanity. The Church
united the divided nations, created out of a multitude of turbulent
tribes a brotherhood of peoples, made the hostile kingdoms become a
single Christendom. Modern Europe without the Church were
inconceivable; whatever most distinguishes her, whatever she most
admires, she owes to the Church. Her stamp is on the literature of
every modern people; the drama rose out of her miracle plays; it was
her faith {657} that bade the first and greatest of modern epics live,
and that will not let it die. Art was her peculiar creation; she
inspired the genius of the builder, and he built the large faith he
lived by into cathedral and monastery; her vivid and fruitful
imagination formed the painter, and the wondrous beauty of his work
but witnesses to the sublimity of her spirit and the truth of her
beliefs. Her mysteries, the sacraments, and miracles that offend the
prosaic rationalism of a godless age, disclose their true
significance, their power at once to awe, to humble, and to uplift,
when seen reflected in the mirror of mediæval art. Science, too, the
Church had made; her sons loved, and cultivated, and enlarged it when
the world was dark, and kings and nobles lived but for war and
plunder. All beneficent and ameliorative agencies were of her making:
hospitals, charities, schools, colleges, the laws that shielded the
serf from the savagery of his master. For all this, and kindred work,
her very constitution qualified her. The clergy had no land, no home,
no worldly affections, no secular care, were separated to her service,
consecrated wholly to her ends, which were those of man's highest
good. Her very organization showed her to be the bearer and organ of
divine truth, throughout adapted to secure its recognition and
realization among men. For above all stood the supreme Pontiff, the
spiritual Sovereign, source of unity, law, order, directing the
energies, formulating the judgments, determining the faith of the
Church; so much the Vicar of God as to be His voice become audible;
gifted with speech that he might control kings and command peoples,
maintain religion, and compel obedience. What the Church had been the
Church would continue to be; she had saved Europe when Rome perished,
and would save it again even though it were out of the very jaws of
the destroyer.
3. Such, in hurried outline, was the historical
Apologetic, at once confirmatory and illustrative of the theoretical.
So far as it is historical its truth is frankly admitted. It is
significant that the purely historical mode of viewing and
representing the matter rose outside Catholicism; was due to liberal
and scientific thought, not to ecclesiastical and polemical. To it,
looking only from the historical point of view, it seemed hardly
possible to exaggerate the obligations of Europe to Catholicism. The
Catholic Church in the Middle Ages did noble work for humanity;
moderated for the old world the miseries of dissolution, moderated for
the new the perhaps still greater miseries of organization and
evolution. But justice to mediæval must not make us unjust to modern
history. The question was not what the Catholic Church had done in the
early or middle centuries, but what it had done in the modern? An
organization that had served and saved a society penetrated with pagan
ideas, may be little qualified to serve a society possessed and moved
by Christian ideals. Laws good for childhood may be bad for manhood;
what makes a man of a child is {658} excellent, but what makes a child
of a man is evil. The Apologists were as weak in the modern as they
were strong in the mediæval question. In the one case they were
eloquent and philosophic about the Church and its work; in the other,
they were reproachful and severe concerning the pride and wickedness
of man. They did not see that there was an absolute change in the
conditions; in the earlier period it was the secular empire that had
broken down, but in the later it was the spiritual. In the days of
Roman decadence and mediæval upbuilding the Church had indeed been an
ameliorative agency and an architectonic power; but in the days of the
Reformation and Revolution it was the Church that had fallen into
feebleness. The Europe she claimed to be alone able to reorganize and
restore, was the very Europe that had become disorganized in her own
hands. She was in the place of the Roman Empire, while the modern
spirit was claiming to occupy hers. The Pope was the new Julian; De
Maistre the new Libanius. As a simple matter of fact, the very revolt
of the intellect was the gravest possible reflection on the capacity
of the Church. The intellect had been in subjection for centuries; to
allow it to escape implied infirmity in the ruler, deficiency in
wisdom, inefficiency of energy and will. The claim of infallibility is
a tremendous claim, not because of what it requires from man, but
because of what it demands in and from the Church. Infallibility in
truth is significant when conjoined with infallibility in wisdom, but
the one without the other is insignificant enough. To be under it is
like being under a creator, almighty but not all-wise; to possess it
is, as it were, to have the mechanical gift, the skill to make
instruments, but not the political, the power to handle and govern
men. For if the revolt of the sixteenth century were a sin, the men
who achieved it were not the only sinners—still guiltier was the
Church that made it possible, that allowed it to become actual. During
centuries she had been supreme; hers had been the hands that made the
men, hers the mind that made Europe; and if the issue of all her
doings and endeavours were the revolt, could she be guiltless, or as
wise as she must be to make her infallibility of any avail, make it
anything more than an ability to do great things if she only knew how?
But more: why had the revolution happened? and why amid so much
hideous terror and blood? Modern philosophy was not altogether or
alone to blame; neither was suppressed and expatriated Protestantism.
The men were sons of France, France was the eldest son of the Church,
and the son ruled as the Church had taught him, with results dreadful
to both. The responsibility for the horrors of the Revolution does not
lie with its principles, but with its causes; and who will now say
that to these causes the Church did not powerfully contribute? But if
she were a contributary cause, what becomes of her claim to the sole
ability to {659} organize and order the modern because she had ordered
and organized the mediæval world? To be a cause of the evil is hardly
equivalent to the power to cure it. The philosophy of history is
guided in its judgments by rigorous and impartial principles. It
cannot, merely in the interest of dogma or sect, accord or deny honour
to a Church; but the honour it accords at one period may be changed
into deepest blame at another. The very reasons that lead it to praise
the work and services of early and mediæval Catholicism, compel it to
hold the later Catholicism mainly responsible for evils the Revolution
was needed to cure.
If the historical doctrine was no good philosophy
of history, still less was the theoretical a good philosophy of
religion. To base religion on authority is the most fatal of all
scepticisms. The arguments that prove it, prove man possessed of an
inherent and ineradicable atheism of nature. But what is to be said on
this point can better be said later on. Enough to remark here, the new
Apologetic was an apologetic for Catholicism, not for Christianity.
Its interest was the Church, not the religion, at least the religion
only so far as identical or co-extensive with the Church. This gave to
it its two most distinctive characteristics—it was political or
sociological and historical. It was a theory of society and the State
applied to and illustrated by specific periods and events in history.
It was a speculation as to the best methods for the creation and
maintenance of order. De Maistre, as has been well said, was a
publicist, and looked at the whole matter from the publicist's point
of view. He was a sort of ecclesiasticized Hobbes, with the strength,
courage, keenness, directness, and, we may add, coarseness of the
original, only with the Pope substituted for the king. But even so the
system had its place, and did a not unneeded or ignoble work. It did
for the Papacy what Hobbes had done for the Monarchy, formulated a
theory of government where order was created by absolute authority
being given to the one, and absolute subjection to the many. Both
marked the reaction that succeeded revolution, though in the one case
the revolution was religious, an attempted reign of the saints; in the
other secular, an attempted reign of reason. It was no less
characteristic that the theory opposed to the religious revolution
based authority on might, but the theory opposed to the secular, based
might on authority. Hobbes' king created the church, but De Maistre's
church created the king. Yet each is explained by its occasion. The
Restoration would have been incomplete without the Leviathan; the
Catholic revival and the counter-revolution had been unjustified
without Ultramontanism. {660}
II.
1. We must now pass from the Continental to the
English Catholic movement. The conditions in the two cases were
altogether different. In France the Revolution had been swift,
imperious, destructive; but here the genius of the people, their
prosaic sagacity, and insular pride, sobered and disciplined by the
long struggle towards completer freedom, first held it at bay, then
graduated its approach, and, at last, peacefully and legally
accomplished it. Hence the Catholic revival could not appear here as
the counter-revolution, as source and ground of order to a disordered
State; for order reigned, and our very revolutions had increased
rather than disturbed it. Indeed, our combined freedom and order had
so perplexed and bewildered the hierocratic theorists, that De Bonald
calmly dismissed from consideration the English people, because they
were, "mainly on account of their defects, by far the most backward of
civilized peoples," and De Maistre described our constitution as "an
insular peculiarity utterly unworthy of imitation." But even here the
forces of change were active, and their movement was the more
resistless that it was so regulated and, as it were, so
constitutional. They were immanent forces, not in the air simply, but
embedded in the customs and habits, laws and institutions, mind and
method of the English people. They were universal, supreme; governing
the men who governed. While they appeared political, they were really
religious; threatened the Church even more than the State; questioned
the accepted principles, doctrines, facts, and authorities in religion
much more severely than the ancient and established in politics. These
forces in their collective and, as it were, corporate character,
constituted what was termed "Liberalism," which was the milder but
more fatal English for the fiercer but less insidious Gallican "Revolution."
If, then, they were held to be forces mischievous in character, evil
in tendency, and ruinous in result, to resist them was a most manifest
and absolute duty. But how? The Sovereign could not, for the Sovereign
was simply the greatest subject in the realm, the creation of its
laws; nor could the Parliament, for it was but the nation in Council;
nor could the Church, for the Church was the people's, rather than the
people the Church's. There was nothing then to hinder the people, were
they so minded, from doing wrong even to the abolition of the law and
worship of God. It was necessary, therefore, to discover an authority
able to bridle and govern the forces of change. God was the supreme
authority; the Church in which He lived and through which He worked
was His visible presence; in it, therefore, the Divine authority must
dwell. This the English people had hitherto been negligent or
unconscious of; only here and there a Catholic divine had understood
and believed; {661} but once make it thoroughly evident, and men, no
longer ignorantly free to believe and worship as they pleased, will
feel bound to hold the faith and obey the law of God.
This was, in brief, the genesis of the Anglican
movement. While formally and incidentally affected by many collateral
influences—the romances of Scott, which supplied it with an
idealized past, and inspired the passion still further to idealize it;
the speculation of Coleridge, which touched it with mysticism, and
imparted, in some degree, the gift of spiritual insight; the poetry of
Wordsworth, which revealed the symbolical and sacramental significance
of common things—yet it was essentially religious, an attempt, in a
period of sifting and change, to find a stable ground on which to
build the faith, an absolute authority by which to govern the life,
first of the individual, next of the nation. It assumed that the truth
of God did not live in the common reason, or His authority reign in
the collective conscience; and that, without a special organ or
vehicle for their transmission and embodiment, they could not continue
to live and reign at all. What was needed was an authority—valid,
visible, supreme. To be supreme, it must be religious; to be visible,
it must be a realized polity or constituted society; to be valid, it
must have independent legislative and efficient executive powers. With
these attributes the Anglican Church was invested, but they were too
immense for her; she bent and failed beneath the burden. Her weakness
but set off the strength of Catholicism. What the one Church could not
bear was the very vital principle of the other; she had for centuries
been testifying her possession of it to the perverse and incredulous
English people. The ancient cause of offence became the new feature of
commendation, and those who felt that they could not believe and be
Christian without authority found in her bosom the authority they
needed.
2. The English Catholic movement, then, was
distinguished from the Continental by its personal and religious,
rather than national and political, character. The publicist view did
not exist here; the conditions did not call for it. But what national
events occasioned in France, personal experiences accomplished in
England. The arena of action and change was subjective, minds that had
felt the unsettling influence of the critical and progressive
tendencies then active, and feared for religion in the degree that
they loved it. The revolution that was dreaded was internal, in the
region of thought and belief. Superficial readers of the "Apologia"
have wondered at the determinative influence attributed to such
incidents as the Jerusalem Bishopric; but, in truth, nothing could be
more just than the place assigned to it, or more impressive and
significant. It was not only a fact fatal to a theory; but Newman's
mind had become hyper-sensitive, it had lost the sense of proportion;
{662} little things troubled even more than large; and his doctrine of
the Church had become so nearly equivalent to the truth of religion
that what touched the one seemed to threaten the other with ruin and
disaster. It had become a matter of personal necessity that he find an
immutable and infallible Church in order to have a stable and true
religion. This need was altogether distinctive of him and the men he
moved, and belongs, as it were, to their natural history, not to the
nation's. It did not rise out of the native conservatism of the
English people, seeking to find the religious principle or
constitutional doctrine that could best resist the tides of
revolutionary thought and action; but it rose in the spirits and out
of the experiences of men who believed that religion could not be
saved, either for themselves or the people, unless in the strength of
a greater and more efficient authority than any their Church knew or
could allow. Hence the English Catholic movement proceeded from and
expressed the religious necessities of persons, not the needs of the
State or the aspirations of the people. And what it was, it is—a
thoroughly individual movement, with less national promise than even
at first, and, what we may term its fundamental principle—authority
as the basis of Religion, and this authority as embodied in the
infallible Church of Rome—was formulated to satisfy these individual
needs. What we have now to consider is the validity and constructive
value of this principle, as represented and interpreted by modern
English, as distinguished from Continental Catholicism.
III.
Cardinal Newman [Note
6] is here, beyond question, the representative man, and so it is
through him that we must construe and criticize the principle. Its
acceptance was a necessity to his own faith; he has done more than any
living man to make it a necessity to the faith of others. He is here
regarded under only one aspect, as the disciple and defender of Roman
Catholic authority, that he may be the better and more victorious a
Christian Apologist. We have the right so to regard him. Disciples
have represented him as the {663} foremost apologist of the day; his "Apologia"
was the recognition of his own significance, the history was the
justification of "his religious opinions." There is no man living
whose works are so thoroughly autobiographical; they are but various
illustrations of his own principle—in religious inquiry egotism may
be true modesty [Note 7]. There is
as much autobiography in, to mention no others, the Sermons, the "Discourses
to Mixed Congregations," the "Development of Christian Doctrine," the "Letters
to Dr. Pusey and the Duke of Norfolk," and the "Grammar of Assent," as
in the "Apologia." Indeed, the "Apologia" loses half its significance
when read alone; it needs to be studied in the light of the works,
tracts, essays, lectures, histories and treatises chronologically
arranged. Conscious revelation of self, even when most careful and
scrupulous, hides even more than it reveals; it is the unconscious and
undesigned that testify more truly of a man. Dr. Newman has always
been supremely conscious of two beings—God and himself—and his
works are a history of his successive attempts to determine and adjust
the relations between these two. This is significant; in the heart of
this chief of the English Catholics there is an intense
individualism—indeed, it was the strength of his individualism that
made a Catholic of him. The "Apologia" is the history of an individual
mind; the "Grammar of Assent" is its dialectic—i.e., the
translation of the causes and course of the changes which the history
records into logical forms and reasoned processes. But this exactly
defines the worth and describes the range of Newman's apologetic
work—it is distinctively individual—first explicative of himself,
and then cogent for men who start with his ecclesiastical assumptions
and are troubled with his spiritual experiences and perplexities, not
for those outside the churches, seeking for a reasoned and a
reasonable belief.
In order to a radical and just discussion, it
will be necessary to discover, if possible, Dr. Newman's ultimate
ideas or the regulative principles of his thought, for they determine
not only his ratiocination, but his mode of viewing things, and the
kind and quality of the arguments that weigh with him. He is by nature
a poet, by necessity {664} rather than choice a metaphysician and
historian. Truth finds him through the imagination, is real only as it
comes to him in image and breathing form, a being instinct with life.
And so he hates the abstract and loves the concrete; a truth grows
real to him only when it is so embodied as to speak to the imagination
and fill it. He is ill at ease when the discussion carries him into
the region of abstract principles, happy only when he can handle what
his intellect conceives to be the actual. For the same reason he is
averse to historical criticism. No man had ever less of the analytical
and judicial spirit that must search and sift and separate till the
original and unadorned fact be found. He can well understand the love
that idealizes the past; he cannot so well understand the love that is
so bent on the truth as to be able to analyze and sacrifice the
dearest traditions and beliefs to reach it. He loves the past which
fills and satisfies the imagination, not the one dissected and
disclosed by the critical reason. Now, these characteristics make it a
difficult, almost a cruel, thing to attempt to reach the ultimate
principles that govern his thought. His is a mind to be handled as he
loves to handle things, imaginatively and in the concrete, not coldly
analyzed; but unless his governing ideas are reached, neither his mind
nor his method can be understood.
2. The true starting-point for the critical
analysis and appraisement of Newman's apologetic work is the famous
passage—
"I came to the conclusion that there was no
medium, in true philosophy, between Atheism and Catholicity, and that
a perfectly consistent mind, under those circumstances in which it
finds itself here below, must embrace either the one or the other. And
I hold this still: I am a Catholic by virtue of my believing in a God;
and if I am asked why I believe in a God, I answer that it is because
I believe in myself, for I feel it impossible to believe in my own
existence (and of that fact I am quite sure) without believing also in
the existence of Him, who lives as a Personal, All-seeing, All-judging
Being in my conscience." [Note 8]
The points here noteworthy are—(l) Atheism and
Catholicism are to his own mind the only logical alternatives; (2) he
is a Catholic because a Theist; and (3) a Theist, because he believes
in his own existence, and hears God speak in his conscience. Now, in a
case like this, it is a matter of moment to see how the principle and
the ultimate deduction are related—the process by which he passes
from conscience to God, and from God to Catholicism. It may be true
that "he has not confined the defence of his own creed to the
proposition that it is the only possible alternative to Atheism"; [Note
9] but it is certainly true that he believes it to be the only
real alternative, and his belief looks ever and again through the
joints and fissures of his cumulative argument, especially as pursued
and presented in his {665} great dialectic work. The position, a
Catholic because a Theist, really means, when translated out of its
purely individualistic form, a Catholic in order that he may continue
a Theist; for, as Dr. Newman conceives the matter, Catholicism, though
it did not create Theism, is yet necessary to its continuance as a
belief. "Outside the Catholic Church, things are tending to Atheism in
one shape or another." [Note 10]
The Catholic Church is the one "face to face antagonist," able "to
withstand and baffle the fierce energy of passion and the
all-corroding, all-dissolving scepticism of the intellect in religious
inquiries." [Note 11] As Dr.
Newman conceives the matter, Catholicism is for the race as for the
individual, the only alternative to Atheism, the necessities that
govern the individual governing also the collective experience.
Without Catholicism, faith in God could not continue to live. There
is, therefore, in spite of the conscience, so much latent Atheism in
the nature and, especially, the reason of man, that without an
organization, miraculously created and governed, God would be driven
out of human belief and reverence. A theory of this sort may in a high
degree honour the Church, but in the same degree it dishonours God. If
"the Church's infallibility" be "a provision adapted by the mercy of
the Creator to preserve Religion in the world," [Note
12] then the provision has been not only, as the history of
European thought testifies, singularly ill-adapted to its end, but
implies a strange defect in the original constitution of the world,
and a still stranger limitation, alike in the intensive and extensive
sense, of the divine relation to it.
The relation between Theism and Catholicism being
so conceived the one must be made to involve the other, the Theism
becomes the implicit Catholicism, the Catholicism the explicit Theism.
The question here is, not why the Theism needs the Catholicism, but
how Catholicism is involved in and evolved from the Theism? The
questions are related, for if the how can be found, the why will at
once become apparent. Yet it is necessary to hold them distinct, for
only so can we get at those ultimate principles or ideas we are here
in search of. It seems, at first, curious that the Theism, which does
not need Catholicism for its creation, should need it for its
continuance. One would have thought that what existed before it, and
independently of it, could exist without it; but this is the very
thing the position will not allow. Theism must grow into Catholicism
or die, become Pantheism, or Atheism, or something equally bad, and
unlike the original. If we ask, why? the answer is more or less
rhetorical, a survey of modern schools and tendencies of thought, and
a comparison of their conflict and varieties of opinion, with the
certainty, harmony, and tenacity of Catholic belief. But if we ask,
how the one involves and leads up to the other? we shall find the
concatenation of ideas {666} in Dr. Newman's own mind; what made him
because a Theist a Catholic? Now the answer to this depends on the
answer to a still prior question, Why is he a Theist? What is the
basis and reason of his Theism? He tells us that he came to rest in
the thought of two and two only absolute and luminously self-evident
beings, myself and God [Note 13].
But why was the being of God as certain and luminous to him as his
own? Through conscience, which he holds to be the theistic and
religious faculty or organ in man [Note
14]. "Were it not for the voice, speaking so clearly in my
conscience and my heart, I should be an Atheist, or a Pantheist, or a
Polytheist when I looked into the world." [Note
15] "As we have our initial knowledge of the universe through
sense, so do we in the first instance begin to learn about its Lord
and God from conscience." [Note 16]
In each case the knowledge is instinctive; "the office which the
senses directly fulfil as regards creation" is indirectly fulfilled by
the sense of moral obligation as regards the Creator [Note
17]. It is therefore conscience not as "moral sense," but as "sense
of duty," as "magisterial dictate," which "impresses the imagination
with the picture of a supreme Governor, a judge, holy, just, powerful,
all-seeing, retributive." [Note 18]
As a consequence "conscience teaches us, not only that God is, but
what He is"; "we learn from its informations to conceive of the
Almighty, primarily, not as a God of wisdom, of knowledge, of power,
of benevolence, but as a God of justice and judgment." "The special
attribute under which it brings Him before us, to which it
subordinates all other attributes, is that of justice—retributive
justice." [Note 19] The "creative
principle" and the contents of religion necessarily correspond; the
correlative of the "magisterial dictate" within is the dictating
magistrate without.
Conscience, then, is the theistic and religious
faculty; but what of the intellect, the reason? While "the unaided
reason, when correctly exercised, leads to a belief in God, in the
immortality of the soul, and in a future retribution," "the faculty of
reason," considered "actually and historically," tends "towards a
simple unbelief in matters of religion." The intellect is "aggressive,
capricious, untrustworthy," its "immense energy" must be smitten hard
and thrown back by an infallible authority, if Religion is to be
saved. Its action in religious matters is corrosive, dissolving,
skeptical. [Note 20] Hence while
the conscience creates religion, the reason tends to create unbelief;
the one is on the side of God, the other against Him. Of course he
speaks of "reason as it acts in fact and concretely in fallen man";
but the conscience he speaks of is also the active and {667} actual "in
fallen man." If sin puts either, it must put both, out of court; what
does not disqualify the one as a witness, ought not to be used to stop
the mouth of the other.
3. But why is so different a measure meted out to
the two faculties? The reason must be sought in Dr. Newman's
underlying philosophy. That philosophy may be described as one
empirical and sceptical, qualified by a peculiar religious experience.
He has a deep distrust of the intellect; he dare not trust his own,
for he does not know where it might lead him, and he will not trust
any other man's. The mind "must be broken in to the belief of a power
above it;" to recognize the Creator is to have its "stiff neck" bent [Note
21]. The real problem of the "Grammar of Assent" is, How, without
the consent and warrant of the reason, to justify the being of
religion, and faith in that infallible Church which alone realizes it
[Note 22]. The whole book is
pervaded by the intensest philosophical scepticism; this supplies its motif,
determines its problem, necessitates its distinctions, rules over the
succession and gradation of its arguments. His doctrine of assents,
his distinction into notional and real, which itself involves a
philosophy of the most empirical individualism, his criticism of
Locke, his theories of inference, certitude, and the illative sense,
all mean the same thing [Note 23].
His aim is to withdraw religion and the proofs concerning it from the
region of reason and reasoning into the realm of conscience and
imagination, where the reasons that reign may satisfy personal
experience without having objective validity, or being able to bear
the criticism that tests it. And so he feels "it is a great question
whether Atheism is not as philosophically consistent with the
phenomena of the physical world, taken by themselves, as the doctrine
of a creative and sovereign Power." This is the expression of real and
deep philosophic doubt, which is not in any way mitigated by the plea
that he does not "deny the validity of the argument from design in its
place." [Note 24] Neither did
John Stuart Mill.
We are now in a position to see why to Dr. Newman
Theism involves Catholicity. It does so for two reasons, springing
respectively out of his doctrines of the conscience and of reason. He
interprets {668} conscience as the consciousness of a "magisterial
dictate," the echo within the breast of an authoritative voice
speaking without it; and to him the legitimate deduction is the
organization of the authority in an infallible Church and the
articulation of the voice through its infallible head. But the other
is the more imperative reason: the intellect is not to be trusted;
left to themselves the conscience may succeed at first, but the
intellect prevails at last. There is no possible escape. "Unlearn
Catholicism" and the "infallible succession" is "Protestant,
Unitarian, Deist, Pantheist, Sceptic." [Note
25] The "formal proofs" for the being of God may amount to "an
irrefragable demonstration against the Freethinker and the Sceptic;"
but they are able so "to invalidate that proof" as to " afford a
plausible, though not a real, excuse for doubting about it." And
without Catholicism the doubt is invincible. "When a man does not
believe in the Church, there is nothing in reason to keep him from
doubting the being of a God." "There is nothing between it (the
Church) and Scepticism when men exert their reason freely." [Note
26]
4. Atheism and Catholicity are then to Dr. Newman
the only possible logical alternatives, because, if we are not driven
by the inner to rest in an infallible outer authority, we must follow
whither the intellect leads, and make the facilis descensus Averno.
But what sort of basis have we here for Theism? and what sort of
Catholicism have we built on it? The nature of man is divided, and its
two parts set in contradiction and antagonism to each other. The
conscience is "the aboriginal vicar of Christ, a prophet in its
informations, a monarch in its peremptoriness, a priest in its
blessings and anathemas;" [Note 27]
but the reason is critical, sceptical, infidel, even atheistic. This
division of nature is the death of natural proof; it is a confession
that proof is impossible. He may recognize "the formal proofs on which
the being of a God rests"; but his recognition must be criticized in
the light of his fundamental principle. It is to him entirely
illegitimate. Conscience he holds to be authoritative, but not reason.
He deduces Religion from conscience, but leaves reason to be crushed
and subdued by authority. Now to build Religion on a doctrine that
implies the radical antagonism of these two, is to make their
reconciliation impossible to Religion; the one must be sacrificed to
the other if man is ever to have peace. The Catholicism that achieves
this may be extensive, but is not intensive; may be {669} political
and local, but is not ideal and human; may be externalized authority,
but is not externalized reason. It may include all men, but it does
not include the whole man. But more: the reason within man implies the
reason without him; he develops into a rational being because he lives
in a rational world. To leave the theistic contents of the reason
unexplicated, is to leave the theistic reason of the world unexplored
and unrecognized; only as they are conceived in their correspondent
and reciprocal relations can we have a Theism satisfactory to the
whole nature of man and explicative of the system to which he belongs.
It is only through reason we find an argument of universal validity;
but Cardinal Newman's doctrine is the purest individualism. The
deliverance of his conscience avails for himself—can avail for no
other; it has interest as a fact of personal testimony, but has no
value as a ground of general belief. It is significant, too, as to the
temper of his own mind; in his intellect as he knows it, in his reason
as he interprets it, he finds no Religion, no evidence for the being
of God; he dare not trust or follow it, for its bent is sceptical, and
so he has to invoke the voice of authority to silence and to command.
The need he discovered in history for an infallible Church he had
first found in his own breast.
IV.
Detailed criticism of Dr. Newman's position, with
its various assumptions and complex confusion of thought, is, of
course, here impossible, but it is hardly possible to conceive a worse
basis for a constructive Theism, especially in a critical and
sceptical age. It turns Catholicism into a new and feebler
Protestantism, one directed against the modern movement of mind. The
Freethinker sacrifices religion to reason in one way, by declaring
that his individual mind is the measure of religious truth; the
Catholic does it in another way, by declaring that unless religion
come under the ægis of his Church, it will assuredly perish before
the corrosive action of the intellect. Each position is an awful
degradation of religion, but the latter is the greater; for the
intellect will not, indeed cannot, cease to be active and critical,
and what is declared incapable of resisting its criticism is handed
over to death. There is surely a nobler Catholicism than this, one not
of Rome, but of man, based, not on the excommunication of the reason,
but on the reconciliation of the whole nature, intellect, conscience,
heart, will, to God, and His truth.
1. In Cardinal Newman's position, those elements
that belong to his Apology for Theism must be distinguished from those
that belong to his Apology for Catholicism. They are not only
distinct, but incompatible. Theism is so rooted in his being, that he
must believe in God because he believes in his own existence; but, on
the other {670} hand, his reason is so inimical to Theism that if he
had not become a Catholic, he must have become an Atheist. Now, this
is an important psychological fact, a valuable testimony concerning
personal experience; but when it is erected into a dialectic position
and elaborated into an Apology for Catholicism, as the only possible
permanent form of the Christian Religion, the matter is altogether
changed. It is then necessary to say, the position is at once
philosophically false and historically inaccurate. To exercise the
intellect is to serve God; Religion has been most vital and most
vigorous when the intellect was most critically concerned with it.
This is a simple historical fact. In the "Apologia" [Note
28] it is said: "No truth, however sacred, can stand against it,
(the faculty of reason), in the long run," and the illustration is,
the pagan world when our Lord came. But the intellect in the ancient
world ennobled and spiritualized Religion; the period of its greatest
activity in Greece was also the period when the religious faith became
purest and strongest. The poets made its gods more august, moral,
judicial; Plato made its ideas sublimer, purged its mythology,
transfigured the theistic conception, made the world articulate the
perfect reason, and time sleep in the bosom of eternity; the Stoics,
by finding a moral order in the universe and a moral nature in man,
breathed a new ethical spirit into both their Religion and their race.
In the ancient world the activity of the intellect in the field of
religious knowledge was the life of Religion, and when it ceased to be
active Religion ceased to live. In the days of our Lord, the places
where the intellect was most active were also the places where
Religion was most real. And what was true of the ancient is true of
the modern world. The activity of the intellect has been altogether
beneficent in Religion; its criticism has been but the prelude to
construction; what has died under its analysis has but made room for
higher forms of thought and larger modes of life. Did space allow,
illustration were easy and abundant, especially from the highest of
all regions—the action of speculation on the idea of God. To take
the strongest illustration, it is no paradox to say, the system of
Spinoza was, from the standpoint of the Christian Religion, a greater
benefit to Europe than any—I had almost said than all the
conversions to Catholicism in the seventeenth century, whether of
kings like James II., or men of letters like John Dryden. For it
raised the problem of Theism to a higher platform, directly tended to
enlarge and ennoble the conception of God, to enrich the idea of
Religion, to promote the study and criticism and appreciation of its
work in history, placing it in a higher relation to the nature and
action of God on the one hand, and the spirit and life of man on the
other. When Dr. Newman says {671} that, without Catholicism, we must
proceed "in a dreadful, but infallible succession," from Protestantism
through Deism or Pantheism to Scepticism, or that "outside the
Catholic Church things are tending to Atheism in one shape or other,"
he writes mere rhetoric. The statement might be reversed; the "infallible
succession" might be charged upon Catholicism with quite as much truth
and charity, or rather with more historical warrant and justification.
Pantheism was known in the Golden Age of Catholicism, the Middle Ages;
to it must be reckoned the systems of Scotus Erigena, Meister Eckhardt,
the Dominican, as well as whole Schools of Mystics; the man who
revived it, Spinoza's forerunner, if not master, was another
Dominican, Giordano Bruno. The most pronounced modern materialism was
developed in Catholic France; certain of its earliest masters were
Catholic dignitaries. One of the earliest martyrs to Atheism was the
pupil of Catholic Divines, the whilom priest Vanini. The Deism of
eighteenth-century England was innocence compared with the revived
paganism of fifteenth-century Italy. The man, whom Buckle selected for
special praise as having been the first to apply the rationalist
method to morals and to history, had been a Catholic priest and
preacher. Catholicism converted Bayle, but only to make a more utter
sceptic of him; converted Gibbon, but only to see him recoil into
completer infidelity [Note 29].
All this may be poor enough, but it is after Dr. Newman's manner. Over
against his charge, "outside Catholicism things are tending to
Atheism," I place this as the simple record of fact, verifiable by all
who choose to pursue the necessary inquiries—inside Catholicism
things have often tended to the completest negation. If his argument
be held equal to the proof of the need of infallibility, mine must be
held to prove its perfect insufficiency. Men may need it, but it is
not adequate to their needs; and an inadequate infallibility is
certainly one of a rather fallible order. The arguments are parallel,
but the cases are not. Catholicism professes to be able by its
authority to do what history has proved it unable to accomplish, and
so is justly chargeable with the most serious incompetency; but
Protestantism, making no claim to authority, professing indeed to be
quite without it, may justly refuse to bear the responsibility of
failure. Incompetency in a system like the Roman is the most
invincible disproof of claim; the competence that comes of
supernatural gifts and authority is no part of Protestantism.
2. But Cardinal Newman's position raises another
question—whether an infallible authority, such as he attributes to
the Church and Pope of Rome, and exercised for the purposes he
describes, would {672} be a help or a hindrance to Religion? Would it
make Religion more or less possible, more or less stable and real?
Differences on such matters are as a rule apprehended in their
superficial aspects rather than in their determinative principles and
causes. One of these is the idea of Religion; it is one thing to me,
another to Cardinal Newman. The Catholic criticizes Protestantism as
if it were or professed to be a sort of substitute for Catholicism;
but it is not this, and never can become it. They are not simply
opposites, but incommensurables; the one represents an organized and
finely articulated hierarchical system, legislative, administrative,
administered, able to comprehend men and nations, and cover the whole
life from the cradle to the grave; but the other denotes only an
attitude of mind or the principle that regulates it. Catholicism
claims to be a Religion; Protestantism cannot be truly or justly
either described as making or allowed to make any such claim. It is
simply the assertion of a right to perform a duty, the right of every
man to fulfil the holiest and most imperial of his duties, that of
knowing and believing the God who made his reason, of worshipping and
serving the God who speaks in his conscience. It is significant as the
contradiction and antithesis to a system of collectivism, which
hindered the clear sense of personal relation and responsibility to
God; but the creation of this sense was the work of God alone, and its
realization in Religion was due to His continued and gracious activity
among men. Protestantism is thus only an attempt to make religion
possible, to create the conditions that will permit and require the
Religion of Christ to become actual. It implies the being of this
Religion, but neither creates it, nor represents it, nor embodies it,
only insists on removing whatever hinders God and man, or man and the
Religion, coming face to face, that it may be realized in and through
his spirit. It may be construed to signify the supremacy of reason,
and so it does; but this only means the supremacy of the truth, or, in
religious speech, the sovereignty of God. The reason indeed is not
particular, individual, arbitrary, but universal, law-abiding,
reasonable, the thought which cannot think without following the laws
of its own being, and cannot follow them without finding the truth.
The whole truth may not be found, but what is found is reality, divine
and sovereign to the man who finds it.
In a certain sense, submission to Catholicism is
the victory of unbelief; the man who accepts authority because he dare
not trust his intellect lest it lead him into Atheism, is vanquished
by the Theism he fears. He unconsciously subscribes to the impious
principle, that the God he believes has given him so godless a reason
that were he to follow it, it would lead him to a faith without God.
Now, there is more religion in facing the consequences than in {673}
turning away from them; for the man remains truer to the truth, obeys
the most immediate and inexorable law of God, that given in his own
being. I can understand the man who says: "I do not wish to be either
a Pantheist or Agnostic; but I must be what the best thought and light
within me—beams as they are of the universal and
eternal—determine, and if they conduct me to either Pantheism or
Agnosticism, then to either I will go, obedient to the laws under
which I live and think." But I cannot so well understand or admire the
man who says: "If I follow my reason it will make an Atheist or a
Sceptic of me; therefore, I will flee for refuge to the arms of
infallible authority." There is a harmony, and so a religion, in the
one nature that is absent from the other; the one has faced the
issues, and knows them; the other has evaded their touch, and is
haunted by possibilities he cannot but fear. There is victory, even in
defeat, to the man who has dared the conflict; there is defeat, even
in the rest he wins, to the man who, that he may keep a whole skin,
turns and runs from the battle.
3. But there is another and still deeper
difference, the conception of the Reason. Here the ideas are again
opposite and incommensurable. Dr. Newman's language seems to me often
almost impious, a positive arraignment of the God who gave man his
intellect. I may say, and the saying need not be misunderstood, reason
is to me as holy as his church is to him. It is too godlike to be
inimical to God; scepticism is not the essence but the accident of its
activity; it is critical when confronted by authority or authoritative
formulæ, and it ought to be critical then, but its history does not
record the growth of scepticism, rather narrates the expansion and
elevation of belief. Reason, while realized in individuals, is
universal; while conditioned in its working, it is transcendental in
its nature and worth, while it acts in and through millions of natural
agents it has a supernatural source and end. It represents law, while
authority represents the violation of law; the one expresses an order
instituted of God, but the other man's most violent attempt at its
suspension or supersession. Hence reason is here conceived as
essentially architectonic, its action where most analytical is always
with a view to a more perfect synthesis. It cannot realize its idea,
or be itself without being constructive. Every attempt to do justice
to it has emphasized this, as of its very essence, that without which
it could not be reason. Take, for example, Kant. He and Newman have
been compared or rather contrasted as, respectively, the one the
source of modern scepticism and agnosticism, and the other the ideal
teacher of religion. But the positions ought to be reversed; Kant is
the great teacher of faith, Newman, in the region of the reason or the
intellect, is the master of scepticism. Kant's reason was
architectonic, made Nature, supplied the forms and the conditions of
thought by which alone she {674} was interpretable and interpreted.
Reason was a latent or implicit universe, real in its very ideality,
so determining phenomena as to constitute a cosmos. But where Kant
treads firmly, Newman walks feebly, speaks of instinct and
presumption, and feels as if he dare not trust reason with Nature lest
he have to trust her with more. Kant, indeed, does not allow that the
mere or pure reason, which is equal to the interpretation of Nature,
is equal to the cognition of God, and he builds, like Newman, his
argument for the Divine existence on conscience. But to him conscience
is still reason, all the more that it uses the "categorical
imperative," and his argument, unlike Newman's, is reasoned; it is not
the mere echo of a "magisterial dictate," but is based on a universal
principle, and articulates a complete theory of moral sovereignty and
government. With Kant the practical is not the contradiction of the
pure reason; the one is but the supplement of the other. They are
conceived by their author not as mutually independent, still less as
opposed, but as so constituting a unity and a synthesis that what the
one did for Nature the other does for eternity and God. But Newman
finds a dualism in Nature that he has to introduce a Deus ex
machina to rectify. Conscience demands God, but reason will not
allow the faith in Him to live, and so an infallible church is called
in to determine the issue, confirm and support the conscience, and "preserve
religion in the world" by so restraining "the freedom of thought" as "to
rescue it from its own suicidal excesses." [Note
30] This may be a good excuse for authority, but it is a bad
apology for faith. He who places the rational nature of man on the
side of Atheism, that he may the better defend a church, saves the
church at the expense of religion and God [Note
31].
A. M. FAIRBAIRN.
Top | Contents | Works
| Home
Notes
1. What is here described as the literature of
the new Catholic Apologetic, may be held as represented by the
following:—M. De Maistre: "L'Eglise Gailicane" (Ed. 1882), "Les Soirées
de Saint Petersbourg" (Ed. 1874), "Du Pape" (Ed. 1819). M. De Bonald "Théorie
du Pouvoir Politique et Religieux dans la Société Civile," "La
Legislation Primitive" (Ed. 1819). M. Chateaubriand: "Genie du
Christianisme" (Ed. 1802). M. de Lamennais: "Essai sur l'Indifference
en Matiére de Religion" (Ed. 1859). This literature may be said to be
devoted to the exposition of the function of Catholicism in an age of
revolution, and so represents what we have termed the new Apologetic.
Good examples of the older are:—Houtevile: "La Religion Chret. prouvée
par les faits" (1740). 3 vols. Bergier: "Traité Historique et
Dogmatique de la Vraie Religion" (1780). 12 vols.
Return to text
2.
"Soirees," vol. i. p. 442.
Return to text
3.
Ibid. p. 403.
Return to text
4.
Ibid. p. 243.
Return to text
5.
"Essai l'Indifference," vol. iv. pp. 242-3.
Return to text
6.
If the subject had been Apologetics by English Catholics, instead of,
as it really is, English Catholicism as an Apologetic, there are many
men I should have liked gratefully to review, such as the late Dr.
Ward and Mr. Lilly, who have each had in the first paper a most brief
notice, but to them would have been added the late Father Dalgairns, a
thinker of exquisite subtlety and refinement, Mr. St. George Mivart,
Father Harper, and others hardly less worthy of regard. The extensive
work of the latter, "The Metaphysics of the School" (Macmillan &
Co. 3 vols. 1879-84), deserves a more careful criticism than it has
yet received. Its worth for the historical student is considerable,
but its polemical, critical, and constructive parts, though most
painstaking and laborious, are of another order and quality than the
expository. Thomas Aquinas is indeed more real and intelligible in his
own Latin than in any English exposition. He is in the one case a
living teacher, handling relevant problems, holding his own place in
history, determining much both of the form and matter of later
thought; but in the other case he is only an adapted teacher, not very
capable of the sort of adaptation he has received, rather lustily
resisting it, justly refusing to be forced to shed light on problems
that had not emerged in his own day. Descartes, Hume, and Kant are not
to be so answered and superseded; their questions underlie the "Metaphysics
of the School," determining alike their possibility and worth, and
Father Harper's criticisms are incidental and verbal rather than
material and real. He must go to work in a more radical fashion, both
in the criticism of modern philosophy and the adaptation of the
schoolman, before he can effect either the displacement of the one or
the substitution of the other. Yet we gladly acknowledge that the
increased attention, so largely due to the present Pope, now being
paid in Catholic schools to Thomas Aquinas, is a most hopeful sign for
Catholicism. Cardinal Zigliara's beautiful edition of the "Opera Omnia,"
now being published at Rome, promises, in spite of the truly Roman
bigotry which the dedication shows to have had to do with the
inspiration of the enterprise, to be a great help to the student of
philosophy and theology; and the number of treatises which have within
the last few years appeared on Aquinas shows that the Æterni
Patris is bearing abundant fruit.
Return to text
7.
"Grammar of Assent," p. 384 (fifth ed.). Cf. Mr. Lilly s "Ancient
Religion and Modern Thought." p. 48.
Return to text
8.
"Apologia," p. 198 (ed. 1883).
Return to text
9.
Mr. Lilly's letter, "Grammar of Assent," p. 500.
Return to text
10.
"Apologia," p. 244.
Return to text
11.
Ibid., p. 243.
Return to text
12.
Ibid., 245.
Return to text
13.
"Apologia," p. 4.
Return to text
14.
"Grammar of Assent," pp. 105-110, 389; fifth edition.
Return to text
15.
"Apologia," p. 241.
Return to text
16.
"Grammar of Assent," p. 63.
Return to text
17.
Ibid., p. 104.
Return to text
18.
Ibid., pp. 105-110.
Return to text
19.
"Grammar of Assent," pp. 390-391.
Return to text
20.
"Apologia," pp. 243-246. Cf. Discourses to Mixed Congregations,
p. 283.
Return to text
21.
"Discourses to mixed Congregations," pp. 275-276.
Return to text
22.
Mr. Froude, in a for him rather innocent way, describes the "Grammar"
as "an attempt to prove that there is no reasonable standing-ground
between Atheism and submission to the Holy See."—"Short Studies,"
second series. p. 83. If he had said—"a book intended to show how a
sceptic in philosophy could, in the matter of Religion, find no
standing-ground," &c., &c., he would have been nearer the
truth.
Return to text
23.
The philosophical scepticism is, of course, implicit not explicit.
From the latter he has tried carefully to guard himself; Cf.
Gram., 64. In this connection ought to be studied the paragraphs pp.
60-61 which the late Dr. Ward thought a veiled attack on himself.—"Philosophical
Theism," vol. i. pp. 30-31. The two men were alike in their religions
profession, but not in their philosophical principles. The sort of
analysis in which Dr. Ward delighted was not agreeable to Dr. Newman;
it savoured too much of the abstract and a priori to please so
great a lover of the concrete and experimental. And Dr. Ward's trust
in his faculties and their avouchments came nearer a belief in the
sufficiency of reason than Dr. Newman liked to go.
Return to text
24.
"University Sermons," p. 194. Cf. Mr. Lilly, p. 99.
Return to text
25.
"Discourses to Mixed Congregations," p. 283. Cardinal Newman here but
repeats Lamennais, see supra p. 4. It is interesting to compare
the agreements of the "Essai l'Indifference" with those of the "Grammar"
and the "Apologia." They differ in some important respects, but in one
fundamental point they agree—their philosophical basis for the dogma
of authority is the most absolute of all scepticism—doubt of the
sanity and divine contents of human reason. They believe in its native
and ineradicable Atheism.
Return to text
26.
Ibid., pp. 262, 263, 283.
Return to text
27.
"Letter to the Duke of Norfolk."—"Anglican Difficulties," vol. ii.
p. 248.
Return to text
28.
P. 243.
Return to text
29.
I hesitated long about Gibbon; but after carefully weighing the
statement in the "autobiography," and one or two significant passages
in the "Decline and Fall," I determined to let his name stand. Yet the
argument does not depend on one or two names: it represents tendencies
operative through centuries.
Return to text
30.
"Apol." 245.
Return to text
31.
The above must not be construed into an endorsement of Kant's
position. The earlier discussions will have shown that the writer as
little accepts it as Dr. Newman's. The philosophy that bases the
belief in God on conscience must resolve religion into morality. This
was what Kant did, and Newman even tends to do, with this
difference:—Kant's moral religion was at once natural and
transcendental; Newman's is positive and legislative; the former was
inseparable from the ideal of humanity; but the latter is
institutional, comes ab extra. Kant's position is the
vindication of faith through Nature; Newman's is the surrender of
Nature to unbelief.
Return to text
Top | Contents | Works | Home
Newman Reader Works of John Henry Newman
Copyright © 2007 by The National Institute for Newman Studies. All rights reserved.
|